In 1947, in the immediate aftermath of the Second World War, Heidegger publicly addressed the concept of evil. He did so in âLetter on âHumanismââ and the passage in question is so enigmatic that it has been largely ignored in spite of the evident importance of the topic. In fact, there is reason to believe that Heidegger did not mean his readers to understand this part of the text at that time. The keys to understanding the passage were not provided until much later. These keys are to be found in the lectures on Schelling from 1936, first published in 1971 (GA 42), and in âEvening Conversation in a Prisoner of War Camp in Russia, between a Younger and Older Man,â dated 8th May 1945, the day on which the Allied Powers accepted the unconditional surrender of Germany, but not published until 1995 (GA 77).1 I am leaving for another occasion the question of how these sentences might impact the debate around Heideggerâs politics. In the present essay, I will confine myself to the task of trying to understand the four sentences on evil from âLetter on âHumanismââ using these additional resources.2
The sentences in question read: âWith healing, evil appears all the more in the clearing of being. The essence of evil does not consist in the mere badness of human action, but rather in the malice of rage. Both of these, however, the healing and raging, can essentially occur in being only insofar as being is itself what is in strife. In it is concealed
164
the essential provenance of nihilation [Nichtens]â (GA 9: 359/272). I will take each sentence in turn, but first I must say a word about âEvening Conversation.â
IHeideggerâs âEvening Conversationâ opens with a discussion of the experience of healing, a discussion that begins with the younger prisoner of war announcing that he has had an experience of the vast Russian forest that was enigmatic to him but that gave him a sense of healing (GA 77: 205/132). The older of the two men identified this sense of healing with a sense of freedom in spite of the fact that they were both prisoners of the Russians. He was also the one who introduced into the conversation âthe devastation [Verwüstung] of the earth and the annihilation of the human essence,â saying that devastation here meant that âeverything â the world, the human, and the earth â will be transformed into a desert [Wüste].â This, he added, is something evil (GA 77: 211/136). According to âEvening Conversation,â the nature of the devastation as something evil becomes more apparent in the experience of the forest as healing. The desert and the forest are both vast expanses where ânothing is encountered that bends our essence back on itselfâ (GA 77: 205/132), but only the experience of the forest is described as healing. This suggests that if we could come to understand the relation of the forest to the desert, then we might have some understanding of the first of the four sentences on evil in âLetter on âHumanismââ, the sentence which reads âWith healing, evil appears all the more in the clearing of being.â The relation between the forest and the desert comes into focus when we approach it through the transformation that the idea of the devastation undergoes in âEvening Conversation.â
This transformation begins when the devastation is no longer conceived exclusively in terms of âwhat is visible and tangibleâ but as something evil (GA 77: 207/133). The transformation is marked by the way that the devastation is no longer conceived in terms of a body count or in terms of the destruction of cities, but is referred instead to the desert understood as âthe abandoned expanse of the abandonment
165
[Verlassenheit] of all lifeâ (GA 77: 212/137). The pursuit of what are ordinarily conceived to be the highest goals of humanity â progress, equal employment opportunities for everyone, the uniform welfare of all workers, and so on â conceal the devastation (GA 77: 211/136). This means that one can spread devastation under the guise of doing good. As the younger man explained: âUnder the appearance of a secured and improving life a disregard â if not indeed a barring â of life could occurâ (GA 77: 213/138). Heideggerâs central point here was that these efforts to improve life, arising as they do out of a high regard for life, belong to the annihilation of the human essence insofar as they take life as the ultimate value. This takes us to the heart of Heideggerâs confrontation with Nietzsche where, on the basis of his account of the history of being, he proposed that, beginning with Hegel, but culminating in Nietzsche, being is thought of as life (GA 47: 318/157). Indeed, in âEvening Conversationâ it is said that in occidental thinking âlifeâ coincides with âbeingâ since ancient times (GA 77: 213/137). If we put all that together, we can see that Heidegger, speaking through the older man, suggests that if what are often conceived as the highest goals of humanity can also be seen in terms of the abandonment of life and thus in terms of the abandonment of being, then being is ambiguous (GA 77: 213/138).
The desert is Heideggerâs word for âthe deserted expanse of the abandonment of all life,â that is to say, of the abandonment of being (GA 77: 212/137). But to complete the transformation of how Heidegger thinks the devastation, he recognized that to think it in terms of the abandonment of being is already to think it being historically (seinsgeschichtlich), and that is to think it in terms of the clearing of being, which, from Heideggerâs perspective, is already to think it in terms of a healing insofar as the clearing is what occidental thinking failed to think and so is what points beyond the history of Western metaphysics as such. The desert and the forest are not simply opposed to each other. In Heideggerâs metaphorics (if one were allowed to speak of such a thing, which of course Heidegger resists), the forest is associated with the clearing. Heideggerâs frequent association of the experience of the
166
clearing with the free points in the same direction, given the claim that the experience of the forest is described as an experience of freedom. Hence one can say that it is in and out of the experience of the forest that the desert is experienced as such. The forest and the desert are intimately connected.
This means that when in âLetter on âHumanismââ Heidegger wrote that âWith healing evil appears all the more in the clearing of Being,â he was not only summarizing the fundamental thrust of the first part of the âEvening Conversation,â but also formulating what he elsewhere called âthe saying of a turning.â This interpretation is supported by the way he had introduced the idea of healing earlier in âLetter on âHumanismââ by suggesting that what is distinctive about the world-epoch in which we belong is the closure of the dimension of healing, a dimension that remains closed âif the open region of being is not cleared and in its clearing is near to humansâ (GA 9: 351â52/267). The experience of healing is thus an indication of a transformation in the relation to the open region of being, that is to say, to the clearing. This interpretation is vindicated by the later stages of âEvening Conversationâ where healing is characterized as a transplanting into knowing. To be sure, at the point of the conversation the discussion has come to focus on the Germans and the knowledge in question is that by which âwe, as those who waitâ are beginning âto turn and enter [einzukehren] the still-withheld essence of our vanquished peopleâ (GA 77: 234/153). âLetter on âHumanismââ is often read without reference to the Second World War, but as soon as its close connection to âEvening Conversationâ becomes apparent, this is no longer possible, and its highly problematic character becomes apparent.
IIThe second of the four sentences reads: âThe essence of evil does not consist in the baseness of human action, but rather in the malice of rage [es beruht im Bösartigen des Grimmes]â (Wegmarken: 189/272). Understanding this sentence must also begin with a reading of âEvening Conversation.â
167
The introduction of âthe malice of rageâ into âLetter on âHumanismââ echoes the shift in âEvening Conversationâ from the discussion of evil to a form of malice in which rage is uppermost (GA 77: 208/134). When the older man suggested that the devastation of the earth and the annihilation of the human essence were evil, the younger man proposed this shift to a discussion of malice so as to mark a turning away from issues of morality. The shift is necessary to avoid misunderstanding: evil cannot be reduced to the morally bad and insight into evil is not granted to those who consider themselves morally superior (GA 77: 209/134). Heidegger here rejected morality as a product of devastation, which it is most of all when morality is directed to world order and world security. This may well strike us as outrageous in the context of the war that had just ended, especially given his expressed desire to separate his discussion of from âthe moral badness of the supposed originators of this devastationâ (GA 77: 209/134), but we cannot see here the legacy of Nietzsche. On the contrary, Heidegger considered Nietzscheâs doctrine of discipline and breeding (Zucht und Züchtung) as an extreme affirmation of morality in the precise sense in which he was dismissing it. According to the younger prisoner, âthe realm of pure will to power is least of all a âbeyond good and evilâ â if there otherwise can at all be a beyond-evilâ (GA 77: 209â10/135). Indeed, in the same place the will itself is said to be evil, but what is meant is not a judgment on the human will as such, but will as a word for being, in the same way that life is a word for being.
What then is to be understood by âthe malice of rageâ? In âEvening Conversationâ the younger man offered this account:
Malice is insurgency [Aufrührerische], which rests in furiousness, indeed such that this furiousness [Grimmige] in a certain sense conceals its rage [Ingrimm], but at the same time always threatens with it. The essence of evil is the rage of insurgency [Aufruhr], which never entirely breaks out, and which, when it does break out, still disguises itself, and in its hidden threatening is often as if it were not (GA 77: 207â8/134).
168
A little later in the dialogue the younger man adds âThe rage [Grimm] which essentially prevails in evil lets loose the insurgency and the turmoil [Wirrnis] that presages on all sidesâ (GA 77: 208/134, tm). These sentences do not on their own offer much clarity and the keywords â ârageâ and âinsurgencyâ â quickly disappear from âEvening Conversation.â
To understand what was meant by both the âmalice of rageâ and âthe insurgencyâ we must go back behind both âLetter on âHumanismââ and âEvening Conversationâ to Heideggerâs 1936 lectures on Schellingâs Philosophical Investigations into the Essence of Human Freedom. Heidegger read Schellingâs essay as an essay on evil and it is, like these two other texts by Heidegger, about evil as, in Schellingâs own words, âa universal activity,â âan unmistakable general principle,â and not a discussion of how evil becomes actual in individuals.3
Heidegger tried to distill into the word Aufruhr what was for him most productive in Schellingâs account of evil. The term can be translated by âinsurgency,â âuprising,â ârevolt,â âsedition,â âinsurrection,â âupheaval,â or âfuror,â but its meaning must be established by the context. Heidegger attempted to summarize Schellingâs account of evil early in the lecture course in the formulation âEvil is the insurgency [Aufruhr] that consists in perverting [Verkehrung] the ground of the essential will into the reversal [Umkehrung] of Godâ (GA 42: 184/106, tm; see GA 86: 223). The word Aufruhr is not found anywhere in Schellingâs text, but the notion of perversion is important there. Schelling referenced Franz Baaderâs account of evil as âa positive perversion or reversal of the principlesâ as a way of not thinking it as in straightforward opposition to the good.4 Heidegger also inserted the word Aufruhr into his interpretation of Schellingâs account of âthe ruin [Zerrüttung] of beingsâ5 to make the point that this perversion is not simply negative. This insurgency against the primal being is rather ânegation placing itself into dominanceâ (GA 42: 247/143).
The word Grimm appears twice in Schellingâs essay and it too was borrowed from Baader, indeed from the very same place in which the latter presented evil as âa positive perversion or reversal of the principles.â Baader had borrowed the word Grimm from Jacob Boehme, who
169
would have found it in Lutherâs translation of the Bible.6 On the second occasion that Schelling used the word Grimm, he did so in his own voice: âeven the most dissolute and false life still remains and moves within God to the extent that he is the ground of existence. But it [this life] perceives him as consuming rage [Grimm] and is posited by the attraction itself in an even higher tension against unity until it arrives at self-destruction [Selbstvernichtung] and final crisis.â7 What is at stake here for Schelling in his account of Godâs consuming rage is the claim that evil is necessary for the revelation of God and that every essence can only reveal itself in its opposite.8 Schelling initially presented this as a formal argument, but he subsequently followed it up in terms of an account of the experience of evil. He described how evil provokes feelings of terror and horror, whereas weakness or incapacity leads only to feelings of regret.9 He argued that these feelings can be explained only if we recognize that sin strives to profane what Baader called the mystery, that is to say, the centrum, which Schelling also identified with the primal will of the first ground.10 But Schelling added that this terror can only be explained because âthe bond of the dependence of all things and the being of God which is before all existenceâ is revealed in sin.11 Hence God as the ground of existence is accessible to âthe most dissolute and false lifeâ as consuming rage through sin. Schellingâs discussion of rage is in this way part of a larger account of how what appears negative can also be taken as something positive. By adopting the word rage Heidegger evoked that discussion, leaving us with the question of how much of that account Heidegger retained in 1947.12
Heidegger in 1936 was quite explicit about his need to distance himself from Schellingâs account. He insisted that by interpreting evil as sin Schelling took the question in a Christian direction. Heidegger, by contrast, wanted to take this questioning of evil toward what he called âthe essence and the truth of Being,â even while admitting that to do so was one-sided (GA 42: 252â3/146). Furthermore, his rewriting of Schellingâs account of decision in terms of resoluteness and his further rewriting of resoluteness in terms of Inständigkeit represented another departure from Schelling, as did the substitution
170
of the moment (Augenblick) for eternity and the disappearance of the account of the terrible in God. Nevertheless, in the context of his reading of Schellingâs essay Heidegger wrote that âevil itself determines a new start [Ansatz] in metaphysicsâ (GA 42: 168/97). This formulation does not repeat the phrase âanother beginningâ that Heidegger had already introduced in the previous year in Introduction to Metaphysics to indicate his own efforts (GA 40: 42/43), but it gave to Schellingâs essay a unique significance.
The fact that Schelling fell back into âthe rigidified tradition of Western thoughtâ by remaining attached to the idea of a system only succeeded in bringing to the fore the difficulties already found at the beginning of Western metaphysics, thereby established the need for âa second beginningâ in relation to the first (GA 42: 279/161). In other words, even though Heidegger was more reserved about Schelling when he returned to him in 1941 (GA 49), one can still read Heideggerâs comments on evil in 1945 and 1947 as an attempt to make good on the promise to make a new start through the reading of Schelling given in the 1936 lectures.
What was Heidegger attempting when he retained from Boehme and Schelling the word Grimm? Heidegger was correct in saying that for all his originality Schelling followed his predecessors by presenting his essay as an attempt to reconcile the capacity for evil with a God who is regarded as pure goodness.13 Nevertheless, it must be acknowledged that Schelling approached God with an extraordinary conceptual novelty by deploying a distinction between being in so far as it exists and the ground of existence, which he had already developed in his philosophy of nature. He argued that God has the ground of existence in himself but that this ground, which precedes God in existence and to which he also gives the name ânature,â is not God.14 One formulation he introduced in an effort to make this idea more accessible was to present the ground as âthe yearning the eternal One feels to give birth to itself.â15 However, at this point Schelling introduced the term will, a term that, as we saw in âEvening Conversation,â not only belonged to
171
the abandonment of being but could also be understood as a word for evil (GA 77: 210/135).
For Schelling God is the unity of the two principles: being in so far as it is and the ground of existence. Evil is their perversion. Among human beings the principles are not indissoluble as they are in God, except in their spirit, and it is through their severability that evil becomes actual. What appealed to Heidegger in his reading of Schellingâs essay was how what was initially presented as the opposition (Gegensatz) of good and evil became transformed into a duality which was separate from all opposition.16 Schelling had been forced at the beginning of the essay to treat opposition and duality as synonymous, but once he had the resources in place to separate them, he had set himself the task âto seek that which lies outside of, and beyond, all opposition.â17 Heidegger shared that ambition, even though his detailed presentation of Schelling in the 1936 lecture course stopped well short of the end of the essay where this happens.
When Heidegger wrote in âLetter on âHumanismââ that âThe essence of evil does not consist in the baseness of human action, but rather in the malice of rageâ he was drawing on Schelling in an effort to move the discussion of evil away from its actuality in individuals toward evil as a universal activity. But he was also attempting to follow Schelling in the way he took up evil as a general principle that is âeverywhere locked in struggle [Kampf] with good.â18 Schelling did not see this struggle as a war. He wrote: âThe passions against which our negative morality wages war are forces of which each has a common root with its corresponding virtue. The soul of all hate is love, and in the most violent wrath [Zorn] only the stillness of the most inner centrum, attacked and excited shows itself.â19
Schellingâs reference to the centrum returns the reader to Baaderâs account, as found in his discussion of rage cited earlier. This account, which highlighted the return of the centrum from the periphery, derived from Boehme.20 Everything points to Boehme as a crucial figure in helping these three thinkers â Baader, Schelling, and Heidegger - move from a perspective that highlighted the kind of negative opposition seen
172
in war to the model of strife, which is what Heidegger now turned to in order to think what he had earlier in the conversation referred to when he said with reference to the thinking of being as life that âthe being of all that is remains ambiguousâ (GA 77: 213/138).
IIIThe third sentence of the paragraph reads: âBoth of these, however, healing and raging [das Heile und das Grimmige], can essentially occur in being only insofar as being itself is in strife [das Sein selber das Strittige ist].â Heidegger in The Origin of the Work of Art had employed the word âstrifeâ to avoid a rigid opposition of world and earth so as to think them âin the intimacy of their simple belonging to one anotherâ (GA 5: 35/26â7). This is why he returned to it in Letter on Humanism to suggest that strife governs the relation of healing and raging.21
Schelling had referenced âstrifeâ in his Philosophical Investigation into the Essence of Human Freedom. For example, he wrote: âFor every essence can only reveal itself in its opposite, love only in hate, unity in strife [Streit]. Were there no severing of principles, unity could not prove its omnipotence; were there no discord, love could not become real.â22 But Boehme had already proposed that life is streitig or strifeful.23 It seems that again Boehme, not Schelling, was Heideggerâs main inspiration here, even if he seemed more ready to accuse Boehme of thinking metaphysically in his account of freedom as belonging to the ground of being than he was to accuse Schelling of doing so on the same subject (GA 86: 232).
Heidegger read Boehme alongside Schelling.24 When Heidegger in 1936 â as part of his exploration of the possibility of a specifically German philosophy â praised the boldness of Schellingâs thinking, he said it was only the continuation of an attitude of thinking which began with Meister Eckhart and is uniquely developed in Jacob Boehme (GA 42: 204/117). Boehmeâs role was crucial. Contrary to a widespread impression, Gelassenheit is more Boehmeâs word than it is Eckhartâs.25 More pertinent in the present context is the fact that Heidegger in his notes on Schelling from the early 1940s quoted from Boehmeâs The Way
173
to Christ: âAnd the visible world is a revelation of the inner spiritual world, out of eternal light and out of eternal shadow, out of spiritual workings. It is a counterthrow [Gegenwurf] of eternity, with which eternity has made itself visible.â26 This led Heidegger to ask: âFrom where and how is evil and torment [Qual], wrath [Grimm] and the anger [Zorn] of God?â Once more attempting to move beyond a negative oppositional thinking toward one based on strife, he answered his own question as follows: âEverything reveals itself only in its counterthrow [Gegenwurf ] â the good only in evil â light only out of darkness â Spirit only in terms of the baseâ (GA 86: 232). Heidegger found in Boehme a different sense of the word Gegenwurf from that which had its source in Tauler and Seuse, where it was employed as a synonym for objectum (GA 6.2: 267/N3: 220). It is clearly not in that sense, but rather in the Boehmian sense, that in âLetter on âHumanismââ in the same passage where Heidegger famously called the human being âthe shepherd of being,â he also called the human being âthe ek-sisting counterthrow of beingâ (GA 9: 343/260).27 And one suspects that for Heidegger what matters is which â being or the human being â is at the centrum and which at the periphery. Heidegger â with Boehmeâs assistance â attempted to move away from human subjectivity in order to think the human being as belonging to being as its counterthrow, just as in Boehme the visible world belongs to eternity as its counterthrow.
IVThe fourth sentence says of the strife: âIn it is concealed the essential provenance of nihilation [Nichtens].â The reference to the nihilating in being was Heideggerâs way of linking the discussion of evil to his thinking of the nothing that had been the topic of âWhat is Metaphysics?â in 1929. That he should attempt this is not surprising, given that âLetter on âHumanismââ, taken as a whole, represents Heideggerâs main attempt to reread his own thinking being-historically from the perspective of another beginning. The remainder of the paragraph from which these four sentences are drawn are devoted to integrating the thinking of the nothing from the 1920s into the thought of
174
the abandonment of being. He wrote: âThe nihilating in being is the essence of what I call the nothing. Hence, because it thinks being, thinking thinks the nothingâ (GA 9: 360/273). Being and Time took as its starting-point the long-forgotten question of being, which implied that the question at least had been remembered so it could be asked anew. This begged the question of how it came to be remembered, but it is a question that he subsequently called die Kehre, the turning, which he referred to the history of being. In âLetter on âHumanismââ Heidegger offered his best answer of how it was possible that in âWhat is Metaphysics?â he thought the oblivion of being (Seinsvergessenheit) as the nothing and then re-thought it being-historically as the abandonment of being (Seinsverlassenheit) (GA 9: 306/233).28
In âLetter on âHumanismââ Heidegger proposed that his own thinking of the nothing was made possible by the strife that joined the healing and the raging in a kind of intimacy. In other words, the thinking of Being and Time was, from this perspective, already in a sense a thinking of evil. A being-historical thinking of evil is possible only in and out of the healing. That the nothing comes to dominance, that the thinking of being happens in our time as a thinking of the nothing, shows the dominance of what he called the unhale (Unheil). The unhale or un-healing, in the sense of âthe closure of the dimension of the holy [des Heilen],â is what is distinctive of this world epoch (GA 9: 352/267). This lies behind Heideggerâs summary of his reflections on evil in the sentence âBeing first grants to healing ascent [Aufgang] into grace, to raging its compulsion [Andrang] to the unhaleâ (GA 9: 360/273, tm). Being grants the healing that enables evil, the unhale, to appear in the clearing of being.29 In other words, Heideggerâs own thinking of the nothing arose from and was a response to the dominance of evil, even if the manner in which he did so was itself, on his own account, to be understood as the happening of a healing.
When a human subject carries out nihilation, it is in the sense of a denial.30 By contrast, when Da-sein nihilates it is âinasmuch as it belongs to the essence of being as that essence in which the human being ek-sistsâ (Wegmarken: 190/273). This ek-sisting is âthe ek-sisting counterthrow
175
of beingâ mentioned earlier and takes us beyond Dasein as the thrown project (geworfene Entwurf) because it highlights the importance of the manner in which Dasein belongs to being. One can approach this from within Baaderâs framework in terms of what stands at the center and what at the periphery. Or, one can approach it in terms more reminiscent of Boehme, as when Heidegger responded to Boehme by writing that âeverything reveals itself only in its counterthrow [Gegenwurf] â the good only in evilâ (GA 86: 232).
The fourth sentence of the sequence that I have isolated from âLetter on âHumanismââ Heidegger says in effect that one must look behind the thinking of the nothing to the strife between healing and the raging for the origin of the nihilating. Being is this strife. But what does that mean for the thinking of evil, especially if one understands as a healing the remembering of what was forgotten in metaphysics (GA 6.2: 439â448/EP 75â83)? The sentence, âWith healing, evil appears all the more in the clearing of being,â is already an answer, albeit one that had already been taken a step further still in the unpublished âEvening Conversation.â
We have already seen how in âEvening Conversationâ Heidegger declared the will to be evil. He meant that insofar as Western metaphysics, thought being-historically, culminates in evil, then Western metaphysics culminates in evil. Indeed, a contemporary text, âThe Anaximander Fragment,â said so directly: in the collapse of thinking into the sciences and into faith the destiny of being (Geschick des Seins) is evil (böse) (GA 5: 353/266). However, the further consequence that he drew in âEvening Conversationâ and put in the mouth of the younger prisoner was that âmalice, as which the devastation occurs, may very well remain a basic trait of being itselfâ (GA 77: 215/139). Heidegger acknowledged that to think that evil dwells in the essence of being represented a challenge. In that text the immediate emphasis was on not becoming pessimistic, but it is also the case, as I have already emphasized, that the claim can be approached only insofar as one has learned to think otherwise, both being-historically and outside of rigid oppositions. Insofar as Heidegger can be read as saying that being is evil, it is, of course, not an identity
176
statement. This is already reflected in his comment in the treatise Das Ereignis about âan âepochâ in the history of being.â He wrote: Being conceals its essence after its emergence in the first beginning; the concealment lets come into being â i.e., now, into âpowerâ â the abandonment of beings by being in the form of beingness as machination. The âagathon,â the âgood,â âisâ its essence: âevilââ (GA 71: 17/10). That in the time of Machenschaft the essence of good is evil means that being withholds itself and the nihilating comes to dominance. But to think this not in terms of opposition but in terms of perversion is possible only insofar as the reversal is happening, because the malice of rage appears in a manner divorced from all morality only with healing.
Because Heidegger seems to have left the thinking of evil to one side after he wrote âLetter on âHumanismââ, it is possible to argue that it occupied him for only a brief interval and that it can be dismissed as a dead end among the thought paths he pursued. But there is reason to believe that it is more fundamental than that insofar as it is intimately connected with the thought that governs the turning, die Kehre. In this regard Heidegger loved to quote Hölderlinâs lines from the poem Patmos:
Wo aber die Gefahr is, wächst
Das Rettende auch.
But where the danger lies, there also grows
That which saves.
These lines are most often cited from their appearance in âThe Question concerning Technologyâ (GA 7: 29/28, 36/34), but their appearance in âWhy Poets?â from 1946, is more revealing for an understanding of âLetter on âHumanismââ. After quoting Hölderlin, Heidegger there commented âPerhaps any salvation [Rettung] other than that which comes from where the danger lies is still within the unhale [Unheil] (GA 5: 296/222, tm). It is a thought rephrased close to the end of the essay: âThe unhale, as the unhale, traces the healing for usâ (GA 5: 319/240, tm).
Heideggerâs insight that when divorced from the will, the thinking of evil as the insurgency of a perversion turns into a conversion, came to him during the course of his profound confrontation with the thought
177
of Boehme and Schelling. It is his insight into the turning, the turning thought being historically. What emerges most clearly is that one can follow this line of thought only insofar as one has met the challenge of abandoning oppositional and calculative thinking. One should not be surprised to find that Heidegger did not expect the readers of âLetter on âHumanismââ to be ready for the idea that being is evil thought in this way. Insofar as they did not, then they would not have understood that for the Heidegger of âLetter on âHumanismââ the thinking of the nothing in Being and Time and in âWhat is Metaphysics?â was already, in a sense unrecognized by Heidegger himself at the time he wrote those works, a thinking of evil. Writing for posterity, he wrote this while holding back the keys that would have allowed his contemporaries to unlock his train of thought there.
There is perhaps no better indication of the gulf separating him from even those who had followed his thought closely than the fact that in 1987 Emmanuel Levinas could ask of Being and Time âCan we be assured, however, that there was never any echo of Evil in it?â31 For Levinas this meant reading Heidegger against Heidegger, reading him with profound suspicion because his silence about the death camps long after the war was over seemed to indicate that he consented to the horror. No doubt Heidegger would have dismissed Levinasâs question as moralistic. But one cannot help but wonder what Levinas might have said in return if he had recognized that, in the four sentences from âLetter on âHumanismââ that I have been investigating, Heidegger made the shocking claim that it is only insofar as there is an echo of evil in Being and Time, that this thinking of the nothing can be said to be a thinking of being at all. According to âLetter on âHumanismââ the very legitimacy of Being and Time, the sense in which it can account for its own possibility, depends on the degree to which one can track the traces of the unhale in it.
178
NOTES1That the Schelling lectures on their own are not enough is well-illustrated by the difficulty Werner Marx has interpreting the discussion without GA 77: Gibt es auf Erden ein Mass? (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1983) 18â19; Is There a Measure on Earth? trans. Thomas J. Nenon and Reginald Lilly (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 30â31.
2One important publication that does take account of these two volumes of GA in order to understand these sentences from âLetter on âHumanismââ is AleÅ¡ Novák, Heideggers Bestimmung des Bösen (Nordhausen: Traugott Bautz, 2011), 99â106. See also Bret W. Davis, Heidegger and the Will (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2007), 293 and Bernd Irlenborn, Der Ingrimm des Aufruhrs. Heidegger und das Problem des Bösen (Vienna: Passagen Verlag, 2000), 222â23.
3F. W. J. Schelling, Ãber das Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit in Philosophische Schriften (Landshut: Philipp Krüll, 1809), 451; Philosophical Investigation into the Essence of Human Freedom, trans. Jeff Love and Johannes Schmidt (Albany: SUNY Press, 2006), 40.
4Schelling, Freedom, 367/35. Baader reprinted the essay in which this phrase is found, âUeber Starres und Fliessendes,â in Beiträge zur dinamischen Philosophie im Gegensaze der mechanischen (Berlin: Realschulbuchhandlung, 1809), 149.
5Schelling, Freedom, 38/34, at GA 42: 248/143.
6Boehme seems to have taken up the word from Lutherâs translation of Psalm 90.7: Martin Luther, Die gantze Heilige Schrift, Bd. 2 (Munich: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag, 1974), 1045. Jacob Boehme himself wrote: âwe lie captive in Godâs wrath [Grimm] between anger and love in great danger.â Sex puncta theosophica, oder Von sechs Theosophischen Punkten, Sämmtliche Werke VI, ed. K. W. Schiebler (Leipzig: Johann Ambrosius Barth, 1846), 357; Six Theosophic Points, trans. John Rolleston Earle (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1971), 47.
179
Schelling, Freedom, 493/66, tm.
8Schelling, Freedom, 452/41.
9Schelling, Freedom, 475-476/55.
10Schelling, Freedom, 442n and 445/35n and 37.
11Schelling, Freedom, 476/55.
12One clear difference between Schelling and Heidegger might well be that for the former we need evil for good to reveal itself, whereas for the latter it is with healing that evil appears all the more in the clearing of Being.
13Schelling, Freedom, 26/24.
14Schelling, Freedom, 429-30/27.
15Schelling, Freedom, 431-32/28.
16Schelling, Freedom, 497/69.
17Schelling, Freedom, 511/77.
18Schelling, Freedom, 451/40.
19Schelling, Freedom, 461/46.
20On the centrum in Boehme, see Aurora, ed. Andrew Weeks (Leiden: Brill, 2013), 20.
21Heidegger described the strife of world and earth here as a Gegeneinander but not as a Gegensatz.
22Schelling, Freedom, 452/41, tm.
23Boehme, Sex puncta theosophica, 355; Six Theosophic Points, 44.
24The only extended study of Boehme and Heidegger I am aware of is Hans-Joachim Friedrich, Der Ungrund der Freiheit im Denken von Böhme, Schelling und Heidegger (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstaat: frommann-holzboog, 2009). Unfortunately, it does not take account of GA 77 and it was too early for GA 86. Furthermore, it does not mention the four sentences from âLetter on âHumanismââ with which I am concerned here.
25See, for example, Von wahrer Gelassenheit, in Der Weg zu Christo, Sämmtliche Werke I, 97â98; trans. 85â136. It seems that the word Gelassenheit appears in only one of Eckhartâs authenticated texts where it is introduced as a synonym for Abgeschiedenheit: Die Rede der Underscheidunge, Die deutschen Werke, Band 5 (Stuttgart: W. Kohlhammer, 1936), 283; The Complete Mystical Works
180
of Meister Eckhart, trans. M. OâC. Walshe (New York: Crossroad, 2009), 514.
26Jacob Boehme, Der Weg zu Christo, Sämmtliche Werke 1, ed. K. W. Schiebler, zweite Auflage (Leipzig: Johann Ambrosius Barth, 1860), 144; The Way to Christ, trans. Peter Erb (New York: Paulist Press, 1978), 185â86, tm. In the same section of GA 86 there is a further quoted phrase from Boehme: ââDie Qual des Abgrund.â It is not from Aurora, as the editor suggests, but from Von dreifachen Leben des Menschen, Sämmtliche Werke IV, ed. K. W. Schiebler (Leipzig: Johann Ambrosius Barth, 1842), 25. Heidegger omitted the final words from that sentence. They read: âsince the self-will and the released [gelassener] will work one with another, as [do] evil and good.â One can speculate that Heidegger stopped the quotation early because he sought to divorce Gelassenheit from the will.
27For this reason, Heidegger in his own copy of Brief über den âHumanismusâ annotated the phrase âthe ek-sisting counterthrow of beingâ with the comment âbesser: im Sein qua Ereignisâ (GA 9: 342/260).
28See further Robert Bernasconi, The Question of Language in Heideggerâs History of Being (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1985), especially 54â57
29The close association of the unhale with evil in the sense of malignancy (der Bösartige) is made clear from some notes on Sophoclesâ Ajax that Heidegger made for a lecture on the Anaximander fragment (GA 78: 305 and 307).
30Heidegger is probably thinking of Sartreâs account according to which the origin of negation is traced to the freedom which reveals itself in anguish: Jean-Paul Sartre, Lâêtre et le néant (Paris: Gallimard, 1943), 71; Being and Nothingness, trans. Hazel Barnes (New York: Philosophical Library, 1956), 34.
31Emmanuel Levinas, âComme un consentement à lâhorrible,â Le nouvel observateur, no. 1211 (28 January 1987): 83; trans. Paula Wissing, âAs If Consenting to Horror,â Critical Inquiry 15: 2 (Winter 1989): 488.
181
RetroSearch is an open source project built by @garambo | Open a GitHub Issue
Search and Browse the WWW like it's 1997 | Search results from DuckDuckGo
HTML:
3.2
| Encoding:
UTF-8
| Version:
0.7.4