Unique positive real number which when multiplied by itself gives 2
"Pythagoras's constant" redirects here and is not to be confused with
Pythagoras number.
Square root of 2The square root of 2 is equal to the length of the
hypotenuseof an
isosceles right trianglewith legs of length 1.
Decimal 1.4142135623730950488... Continued fraction 1 + 1 2 + 1 2 + 1 2 + 1 2 + ⋱ {\displaystyle 1+{\cfrac {1}{2+{\cfrac {1}{2+{\cfrac {1}{2+{\cfrac {1}{2+\ddots }}}}}}}}}The square root of 2 (approximately 1.4142) is the positive real number that, when multiplied by itself or squared, equals the number 2. It may be written as 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} or 2 1 / 2 {\displaystyle 2^{1/2}} . It is an algebraic number, and therefore not a transcendental number. Technically, it should be called the principal square root of 2, to distinguish it from the negative number with the same property.
Geometrically, the square root of 2 is the length of a diagonal across a square with sides of one unit of length; this follows from the Pythagorean theorem. It was probably the first number known to be irrational.[1] The fraction 99/70 (≈ 1.4142857) is sometimes used as a good rational approximation with a reasonably small denominator.
Sequence A002193 in the On-Line Encyclopedia of Integer Sequences consists of the digits in the decimal expansion of the square root of 2, here truncated to 60 decimal places:[2]
The Babylonian clay tablet YBC 7289 (c. 1800–1600 BC) gives an approximation of 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} in four sexagesimal figures, 1 24 51 10, which is accurate to about six decimal digits,[3] and is the closest possible three-place sexagesimal representation of 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} , representing a margin of error of only –0.000042%:
Another early approximation is given in ancient Indian mathematical texts, the Sulbasutras (c. 800–200 BC), as follows: Increase the length [of the side] by its third and this third by its own fourth less the thirty-fourth part of that fourth.[4] That is,
This approximation, diverging from the actual value of 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} by approximately +0.07%, is the seventh in a sequence of increasingly accurate approximations based on the sequence of Pell numbers, which can be derived from the continued fraction expansion of 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} . Despite having a smaller denominator, it is only slightly less accurate than the Babylonian approximation.
Pythagoreans discovered that the diagonal of a square is incommensurable with its side, or in modern language, that the square root of two is irrational. Little is known with certainty about the time or circumstances of this discovery, but the name of Hippasus of Metapontum is often mentioned. For a while, the Pythagoreans treated as an official secret the discovery that the square root of two is irrational, and, according to legend, Hippasus was murdered for divulging it, though this has little to any substantial evidence in traditional historian practice.[5][6] The square root of two is occasionally called Pythagoras's number[7] or Pythagoras's constant.
Ancient Roman architecture[edit]In ancient Roman architecture, Vitruvius describes the use of the square root of 2 progression or ad quadratum technique. It consists basically in a geometric, rather than arithmetic, method to double a square, in which the diagonal of the original square is equal to the side of the resulting square. Vitruvius attributes the idea to Plato. The system was employed to build pavements by creating a square tangent to the corners of the original square at 45 degrees of it. The proportion was also used to design atria by giving them a length equal to a diagonal taken from a square, whose sides are equivalent to the intended atrium's width.[8]
Computation algorithms[edit]There are many algorithms for approximating 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} as a ratio of integers or as a decimal. The most common algorithm for this, which is used as a basis in many computers and calculators, is the Babylonian method[9] for computing square roots, an example of Newton's method for computing roots of arbitrary functions. It goes as follows:
First, pick a guess, a 0 > 0 {\displaystyle a_{0}>0} ; the value of the guess affects only how many iterations are required to reach an approximation of a certain accuracy. Then, using that guess, iterate through the following recursive computation:
Each iteration improves the approximation, roughly doubling the number of correct digits. Starting with a 0 = 1 {\displaystyle a_{0}=1} , the subsequent iterations yield:
A simple rational approximation 99/70 (≈ 1.4142857) is sometimes used. Despite having a denominator of only 70, it differs from the correct value by less than 1/10,000 (approx. +0.72×10−4).
The next two better rational approximations are 140/99 (≈ 1.4141414...) with a marginally smaller error (approx. −0.72×10−4), and 239/169 (≈ 1.4142012) with an error of approx −0.12×10−4.
The rational approximation of the square root of two derived from four iterations of the Babylonian method after starting with a0 = 1 (665,857/470,832) is too large by about 1.6×10−12; its square is ≈ 2.0000000000045.
Records in computation[edit]In 1997, the value of 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} was calculated to 137,438,953,444 decimal places by Yasumasa Kanada's team. In February 2006, the record for the calculation of 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} was eclipsed with the use of a home computer. Shigeru Kondo calculated one trillion decimal places in 2010.[10] Other mathematical constants whose decimal expansions have been calculated to similarly high precision include π, e, and the golden ratio.[11] Such computations provide empirical evidence of whether these numbers are normal.
This is a table of recent records in calculating the digits of 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} .[11]
Date Name Number of digits 4 April 2025 Teck Por Lim 24000000000000 26 December 2023 Jordan Ranous 20000000000000 5 January 2022 Tizian Hanselmann 10000000001000 28 June 2016 Ron Watkins 10000000000000 3 April 2016 Ron Watkins 5000000000000 20 January 2016 Ron Watkins 2000000000100 9 February 2012 Alexander Yee 2000000000050 22 March 2010 Shigeru Kondo 1000000000000 Proofs of irrationality[edit] Proof by infinite descent[edit]One proof of the number's irrationality is the following proof by infinite descent. It is also a proof of a negation by refutation: it proves the statement " 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is not rational" by assuming that it is rational and then deriving a falsehood.
Since we have derived a falsehood, the assumption (1) that 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is a rational number must be false. This means that 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is not a rational number; that is to say, 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is irrational.
This proof was hinted at by Aristotle, in his Analytica Priora, §I.23.[12] It appeared first as a full proof in Euclid's Elements, as proposition 117 of Book X. However, since the early 19th century, historians have agreed that this proof is an interpolation and not attributable to Euclid.[13]
Proof using reciprocals[edit]Assume by way of contradiction that 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} were rational. Then we may write 2 + 1 = q p {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}+1={\frac {q}{p}}} as an irreducible fraction in lowest terms, with coprime positive integers q > p {\displaystyle q>p} . Since ( 2 − 1 ) ( 2 + 1 ) = 2 − 1 2 = 1 {\displaystyle ({\sqrt {2}}-1)({\sqrt {2}}+1)=2-1^{2}=1} , it follows that 2 − 1 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}-1} can be expressed as the irreducible fraction p q {\displaystyle {\frac {p}{q}}} . However, since 2 − 1 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}-1} and 2 + 1 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}+1} differ by an integer, it follows that the denominators of their irreducible fraction representations must be the same, i.e. q = p {\displaystyle q=p} . This gives the desired contradiction.
Proof by unique factorization[edit]As with the proof by infinite descent, we obtain a 2 = 2 b 2 {\displaystyle a^{2}=2b^{2}} . Being the same quantity, each side has the same prime factorization by the fundamental theorem of arithmetic, and in particular, would have to have the factor 2 occur the same number of times. However, the factor 2 appears an odd number of times on the right, but an even number of times on the left—a contradiction.
Application of the rational root theorem[edit]The irrationality of 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} also follows from the rational root theorem, which states that a rational root of a polynomial, if it exists, must be the quotient of a factor of the constant term and a factor of the leading coefficient. In the case of p ( x ) = x 2 − 2 {\displaystyle p(x)=x^{2}-2} , the only possible rational roots are ± 1 {\displaystyle \pm 1} and ± 2 {\displaystyle \pm 2} . As 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is not equal to ± 1 {\displaystyle \pm 1} or ± 2 {\displaystyle \pm 2} , it follows that 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is irrational. This application also invokes the integer root theorem, a stronger version of the rational root theorem for the case when p ( x ) {\displaystyle p(x)} is a monic polynomial with integer coefficients; for such a polynomial, all roots are necessarily integers (which 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is not, as 2 is not a perfect square) or irrational.
The rational root theorem (or integer root theorem) may be used to show that any square root of any natural number that is not a perfect square is irrational. For other proofs that the square root of any non-square natural number is irrational, see Quadratic irrational number or Infinite descent.
Tennenbaum's proof[edit] Figure 1. Stanley Tennenbaum's geometric proof of the irrationality of √2A simple proof is attributed to Stanley Tennenbaum when he was a student in the early 1950s.[14][15] Assume that 2 = a / b {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}=a/b} , where a {\displaystyle a} and b {\displaystyle b} are coprime positive integers. Then a {\displaystyle a} and b {\displaystyle b} are the smallest positive integers for which a 2 = 2 b 2 {\displaystyle a^{2}=2b^{2}} . Geometrically, this implies that a square with side length a {\displaystyle a} will have an area equal to two squares of (lesser) side length b {\displaystyle b} . Call these squares A and B. We can draw these squares and compare their areas - the simplest way to do so is to fit the two B squares into the A squares. When we try to do so, we end up with the arrangement in Figure 1., in which the two B squares overlap in the middle and two uncovered areas are present in the top left and bottom right. In order to assert a 2 = 2 b 2 {\displaystyle a^{2}=2b^{2}} , we would need to show that the area of the overlap is equal to the area of the two missing areas, i.e. ( 2 b − a ) 2 {\displaystyle (2b-a)^{2}} = 2 ( a − b ) 2 {\displaystyle 2(a-b)^{2}} . In other terms, we may refer to the side lengths of the overlap and missing areas as p = 2 b − a {\displaystyle p=2b-a} and q = a − b {\displaystyle q=a-b} , respectively, and thus we have p 2 = 2 q 2 {\displaystyle p^{2}=2q^{2}} . But since we can see from the diagram that p < a {\displaystyle p<a} and q < b {\displaystyle q<b} , and we know that p {\displaystyle p} and q {\displaystyle q} are integers from their definitions in terms of a {\displaystyle a} and b {\displaystyle b} , this means that we are in violation of the original assumption that a {\displaystyle a} and b {\displaystyle b} are the smallest positive integers for which a 2 = 2 b 2 {\displaystyle a^{2}=2b^{2}} .
Hence, even in assuming that a {\displaystyle a} and b {\displaystyle b} are the smallest positive integers for which a 2 = 2 b 2 {\displaystyle a^{2}=2b^{2}} , we may prove that there exists a smaller pair of integers p {\displaystyle p} and q {\displaystyle q} which satisfy the relation. This contradiction within the definition of a {\displaystyle a} and b {\displaystyle b} implies that they cannot exist, and thus 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} must be irrational.
Figure 2. Tom Apostol's geometric proof of the irrationality of √2Tom M. Apostol made another geometric reductio ad absurdum argument showing that 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is irrational.[16] It is also an example of proof by infinite descent. It makes use of classic compass and straightedge construction, proving the theorem by a method similar to that employed by ancient Greek geometers. It is essentially the same algebraic proof as Tennebaum's proof, viewed geometrically in another way.
Let △ ABC be a right isosceles triangle with hypotenuse length m and legs n as shown in Figure 2. By the Pythagorean theorem, m n = 2 {\displaystyle {\frac {m}{n}}={\sqrt {2}}} . Suppose m and n are integers. Let m:n be a ratio given in its lowest terms.
Draw the arcs BD and CE with centre A. Join DE. It follows that AB = AD, AC = AE and ∠BAC and ∠DAE coincide. Therefore, the triangles ABC and ADE are congruent by SAS.
Because ∠EBF is a right angle and ∠BEF is half a right angle, △ BEF is also a right isosceles triangle. Hence BE = m − n implies BF = m − n. By symmetry, DF = m − n, and △ FDC is also a right isosceles triangle. It also follows that FC = n − (m − n) = 2n − m.
Hence, there is an even smaller right isosceles triangle, with hypotenuse length 2n − m and legs m − n. These values are integers even smaller than m and n and in the same ratio, contradicting the hypothesis that m:n is in lowest terms. Therefore, m and n cannot be both integers; hence, 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is irrational.
Constructive proof[edit]While the proofs by infinite descent are constructively valid when "irrational" is defined to mean "not rational", we can obtain a constructively stronger statement by using a positive definition of "irrational" as "quantifiably apart from every rational". Let a and b be positive integers such that 1<a/b< 3/2 (as 1<2< 9/4 satisfies these bounds). Now 2b2 and a2 cannot be equal, since the first has an odd number of factors 2 whereas the second has an even number of factors 2. Thus |2b2 − a2| ≥ 1. Multiplying the absolute difference |√2 − a/b| by b2(√2 + a/b) in the numerator and denominator, we get[17]
the latter inequality being true because it is assumed that 1<a/b< 3/2, giving a/b + √2 ≤ 3 (otherwise the quantitative apartness can be trivially established). This gives a lower bound of 1/3b2 for the difference |√2 − a/b|, yielding a direct proof of irrationality in its constructively stronger form, not relying on the law of excluded middle.[18] This proof constructively exhibits an explicit discrepancy between 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} and any rational.
Proof by Pythagorean triples[edit]This proof uses the following property of primitive Pythagorean triples:
This lemma can be used to show that two identical perfect squares can never be added to produce another perfect square.
Suppose the contrary that 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is rational. Therefore,
Here, (b, b, a) is a primitive Pythagorean triple, and from the lemma a is never even. However, this contradicts the equation 2b2 = a2 which implies that a must be even.
Multiplicative inverse[edit]The multiplicative inverse (reciprocal) of the square root of two is a widely used constant, with the decimal value:[20]
It is often encountered in geometry and trigonometry because the unit vector, which makes a 45° angle with the axes in a plane, has the coordinates
Each coordinate satisfies
One interesting property of 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is
since
This is related to the property of silver ratios.
2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} can also be expressed in terms of copies of the imaginary unit i using only the square root and arithmetic operations, if the square root symbol is interpreted suitably for the complex numbers i and −i:
2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is also the only real number other than 1 whose infinite tetrate (i.e., infinite exponential tower) is equal to its square. In other words: if for c > 1, x1 = c and xn+1 = cxn for n > 1, the limit of xn as n → ∞ will be called (if this limit exists) f(c). Then 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is the only number c > 1 for which f(c) = c2. Or symbolically:
2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} appears in Viète's formula for π,
which is related to the formula[21]
Similar in appearance but with a finite number of terms, 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} appears in various trigonometric constants:[22]
It is not known whether 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} is a normal number, which is a stronger property than irrationality, but statistical analyses of its binary expansion are consistent with the hypothesis that it is normal to base two.[23]
Series and product[edit]The identity cos π/4 = sin π/4 = 1/√2, along with the infinite product representations for the sine and cosine, leads to products such as
and
or equivalently,
The number can also be expressed by taking the Taylor series of a trigonometric function. For example, the series for cos π/4 gives
The Taylor series of 1 + x {\displaystyle {\sqrt {1+x}}} with x = 1 and using the double factorial n!! gives
The convergence of this series can be accelerated with an Euler transform, producing
It is not known whether 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} can be represented with a BBP-type formula. BBP-type formulas are known for π√2 and 2 ln ( 1 + 2 ) {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}\ln(1+{\sqrt {2}})} , however.[24]
The number can be represented by an infinite series of Egyptian fractions, with denominators defined by 2nth terms of a Fibonacci-like recurrence relation a(n) = 34a(n−1) − a(n−2), a(0) = 0, a(1) = 6:[25]
The square root of two has the following continued fraction representation:
The convergents p/q formed by truncating this representation form a sequence of fractions that approximate the square root of two to increasing accuracy, and that are described by the Pell numbers (i.e., p2 − 2q2 = ±1). The first convergents are: 1/1, 3/2, 7/5, 17/12, 41/29, 99/70, 239/169, 577/408 and the convergent following p/q is p + 2q/p + q. The convergent p/q differs from 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} by almost exactly 1 2 2 q 2 {\displaystyle {\frac {1}{2{\sqrt {2}}q^{2}}}} , which follows from:
The following nested square expressions converge to 2 {\textstyle {\sqrt {2}}} :
In 1786, German physics professor Georg Christoph Lichtenberg[26] found that any sheet of paper whose long edge is 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} times longer than its short edge could be folded in half and aligned with its shorter side to produce a sheet with exactly the same proportions as the original. This ratio of lengths of the longer over the shorter side guarantees that cutting a sheet in half along a line results in the smaller sheets having the same (approximate) ratio as the original sheet. When Germany standardised paper sizes at the beginning of the 20th century, they used Lichtenberg's ratio to create the "A" series of paper sizes.[26] Today, the (approximate) aspect ratio of paper sizes under ISO 216 (A4, A0, etc.) is 1: 2 {\displaystyle {\sqrt {2}}} .
Proof:
Let S = {\displaystyle S=} shorter length and L = {\displaystyle L=} longer length of the sides of a sheet of paper, with
Let R ′ = L ′ S ′ {\displaystyle R'={\frac {L'}{S'}}} be the analogous ratio of the halved sheet, then
There are some interesting properties involving the square root of 2 in the physical sciences:
RetroSearch is an open source project built by @garambo | Open a GitHub Issue
Search and Browse the WWW like it's 1997 | Search results from DuckDuckGo
HTML:
3.2
| Encoding:
UTF-8
| Version:
0.7.4