From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Non-contradiction of a theory
In deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction.[1] A theory T {\displaystyle T} is consistent if there is no formula φ {\displaystyle \varphi } such that both φ {\displaystyle \varphi } and its negation ¬ φ {\displaystyle \lnot \varphi } are elements of the set of consequences of T {\displaystyle T} . Let A {\displaystyle A} be a set of closed sentences (informally "axioms") and ⟨ A ⟩ {\displaystyle \langle A\rangle } the set of closed sentences provable from A {\displaystyle A} under some (specified, possibly implicitly) formal deductive system. The set of axioms A {\displaystyle A} is consistent when there is no formula φ {\displaystyle \varphi } such that φ ∈ ⟨ A ⟩ {\displaystyle \varphi \in \langle A\rangle } and ¬ φ ∈ ⟨ A ⟩ {\displaystyle \lnot \varphi \in \langle A\rangle } . A trivial theory (i.e., one which proves every sentence in the language of the theory) is clearly inconsistent. Conversely, in an explosive formal system (e.g., classical or intuitionistic propositional or first-order logics) every inconsistent theory is trivial.[2]: 7 Consistency of a theory is a syntactic notion, whose semantic counterpart is satisfiability. A theory is satisfiable if it has a model, i.e., there exists an interpretation under which all axioms in the theory are true.[3] This is what consistent meant in traditional Aristotelian logic, although in contemporary mathematical logic the term satisfiable is used instead.
In a sound formal system, every satisfiable theory is consistent, but the converse does not hold. If there exists a deductive system for which these semantic and syntactic definitions are equivalent for any theory formulated in a particular deductive logic, the logic is called complete.[citation needed] The completeness of the propositional calculus was proved by Paul Bernays in 1918[citation needed][4] and Emil Post in 1921,[5] while the completeness of (first order) predicate calculus was proved by Kurt Gödel in 1930,[6] and consistency proofs for arithmetics restricted with respect to the induction axiom schema were proved by Ackermann (1924), von Neumann (1927) and Herbrand (1931).[7] Stronger logics, such as second-order logic, are not complete.
A consistency proof is a mathematical proof that a particular theory is consistent.[8] The early development of mathematical proof theory was driven by the desire to provide finitary consistency proofs for all of mathematics as part of Hilbert's program. Hilbert's program was strongly impacted by the incompleteness theorems, which showed that sufficiently strong proof theories cannot prove their consistency (provided that they are consistent).
Although consistency can be proved using model theory, it is often done in a purely syntactical way, without any need to reference some model of the logic. The cut-elimination (or equivalently the normalization of the underlying calculus if there is one) implies the consistency of the calculus: since there is no cut-free proof of falsity, there is no contradiction in general.
Consistency and completeness in arithmetic and set theory[edit]In theories of arithmetic, such as Peano arithmetic, there is an intricate relationship between the consistency of the theory and its completeness. A theory is complete if, for every formula φ in its language, at least one of φ or ¬φ is a logical consequence of the theory.
Presburger arithmetic is an axiom system for the natural numbers under addition. It is both consistent and complete.
Gödel's incompleteness theorems show that any sufficiently strong recursively enumerable theory of arithmetic cannot be both complete and consistent. Gödel's theorem applies to the theories of Peano arithmetic (PA) and primitive recursive arithmetic (PRA), but not to Presburger arithmetic.
Moreover, Gödel's second incompleteness theorem shows that the consistency of sufficiently strong recursively enumerable theories of arithmetic can be tested in a particular way. Such a theory is consistent if and only if it does not prove a particular sentence, called the Gödel sentence of the theory, which is a formalized statement of the claim that the theory is indeed consistent. Thus the consistency of a sufficiently strong, recursively enumerable, consistent theory of arithmetic can never be proven in that system itself. The same result is true for recursively enumerable theories that can describe a strong enough fragment of arithmetic—including set theories such as Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF). These set theories cannot prove their own Gödel sentence—provided that they are consistent, which is generally believed.
Because consistency of ZF is not provable in ZF, the weaker notion relative consistency is interesting in set theory (and in other sufficiently expressive axiomatic systems). If T is a theory and A is an additional axiom, T + A is said to be consistent relative to T (or simply that A is consistent with T) if it can be proved that if T is consistent then T + A is consistent. If both A and ¬A are consistent with T, then A is said to be independent of T.
In the following context of mathematical logic, the turnstile symbol ⊢ {\displaystyle \vdash } means "provable from". That is, a ⊢ b {\displaystyle a\vdash b} reads: b is provable from a (in some specified formal system).
Let S {\displaystyle S} be a set of symbols. Let Φ {\displaystyle \Phi } be a maximally consistent set of S {\displaystyle S} -formulas containing witnesses.
Define an equivalence relation ∼ {\displaystyle \sim } on the set of S {\displaystyle S} -terms by t 0 ∼ t 1 {\displaystyle t_{0}\sim t_{1}} if t 0 ≡ t 1 ∈ Φ {\displaystyle \;t_{0}\equiv t_{1}\in \Phi } , where ≡ {\displaystyle \equiv } denotes equality. Let t ¯ {\displaystyle {\overline {t}}} denote the equivalence class of terms containing t {\displaystyle t} ; and let T Φ := { t ¯ ∣ t ∈ T S } {\displaystyle T_{\Phi }:=\{\;{\overline {t}}\mid t\in T^{S}\}} where T S {\displaystyle T^{S}} is the set of terms based on the set of symbols S {\displaystyle S} .
Define the S {\displaystyle S} -structure T Φ {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {T}}_{\Phi }} over T Φ {\displaystyle T_{\Phi }} , also called the term-structure corresponding to Φ {\displaystyle \Phi } , by:
Define a variable assignment β Φ {\displaystyle \beta _{\Phi }} by β Φ ( x ) := x ¯ {\displaystyle \beta _{\Phi }(x):={\bar {x}}} for each variable x {\displaystyle x} . Let I Φ := ( T Φ , β Φ ) {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {I}}_{\Phi }:=({\mathfrak {T}}_{\Phi },\beta _{\Phi })} be the term interpretation associated with Φ {\displaystyle \Phi } .
Then for each S {\displaystyle S} -formula φ {\displaystyle \varphi } :
I Φ ⊨ φ {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {I}}_{\Phi }\vDash \varphi }if and only if
φ ∈ Φ . {\displaystyle \;\varphi \in \Phi .} [citation needed]There are several things to verify. First, that ∼ {\displaystyle \sim } is in fact an equivalence relation. Then, it needs to be verified that (1), (2), and (3) are well defined. This falls out of the fact that ∼ {\displaystyle \sim } is an equivalence relation and also requires a proof that (1) and (2) are independent of the choice of t 0 , … , t n − 1 {\displaystyle t_{0},\ldots ,t_{n-1}} class representatives. Finally, I Φ ⊨ φ {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {I}}_{\Phi }\vDash \varphi } can be verified by induction on formulas.
In ZFC set theory with classical first-order logic,[10] an inconsistent theory T {\displaystyle T} is one such that there exists a closed sentence φ {\displaystyle \varphi } such that T {\displaystyle T} contains both φ {\displaystyle \varphi } and its negation φ ′ {\displaystyle \varphi '} . A consistent theory is one such that the following logically equivalent conditions hold
Let L {\displaystyle L} be a signature, T {\displaystyle T} a theory in L ∞ ω {\displaystyle L_{\infty \omega }} and φ {\displaystyle \varphi } a sentence in L ∞ ω {\displaystyle L_{\infty \omega }} . We say that φ {\displaystyle \varphi } is a consequence of T {\displaystyle T} , or that T {\displaystyle T} entails φ {\displaystyle \varphi } , in symbols T ⊢ φ {\displaystyle T\vdash \varphi } , if every model of T {\displaystyle T} is a model of φ {\displaystyle \varphi } . (In particular if T {\displaystyle T} has no models then T {\displaystyle T} entails φ {\displaystyle \varphi } .)(Please note the definition of Mod(T) on p. 30 ...)
Warning: we don't require that if T ⊢ φ {\displaystyle T\vdash \varphi } then there is a proof of φ {\displaystyle \varphi } from T {\displaystyle T} . In any case, with infinitary languages, it's not always clear what would constitute proof. Some writers use T ⊢ φ {\displaystyle T\vdash \varphi } to mean that φ {\displaystyle \varphi } is deducible from T {\displaystyle T} in some particular formal proof calculus, and they write T ⊨ φ {\displaystyle T\models \varphi } for our notion of entailment (a notation which clashes with our A ⊨ φ {\displaystyle A\models \varphi } ). For first-order logic, the two kinds of entailment coincide by the completeness theorem for the proof calculus in question.
We say that φ {\displaystyle \varphi } is valid, or is a logical theorem, in symbols ⊢ φ {\displaystyle \vdash \varphi } , if φ {\displaystyle \varphi } is true in every L {\displaystyle L} -structure. We say that φ {\displaystyle \varphi } is consistent if φ {\displaystyle \varphi } is true in some L {\displaystyle L} -structure. Likewise, we say that a theory T {\displaystyle T} is consistent if it has a model.
We say that two theories S and T in L infinity omega are equivalent if they have the same models, i.e. if Mod(S) = Mod(T).
Look up
consistencyin Wiktionary, the free dictionary.
RetroSearch is an open source project built by @garambo | Open a GitHub Issue
Search and Browse the WWW like it's 1997 | Search results from DuckDuckGo
HTML:
3.2
| Encoding:
UTF-8
| Version:
0.7.4